Wednesday 20 June 2012

Externality chains

Are there really no bright line rules separating actions with external costs from those that are properly left entirely to individual choice? David Roberts sees only shades of grey:
Take sodas, for instance: The costs of health care in the U.S. are socialized to some degree, so individual decisions to get unhealthier do affect me. I pay when rates are driven up, or when people end up in the emergency room.
So whatever the line is — between the sphere of rights and sovereign individuality on one hand and the sphere of interconnectedness and social responsibility on the other — it can’t be “actions that don’t affect others.” There are none!
Perhaps, then, the distinction is between actions that mostly affect me and those that substantially affect others. If I dump trash in a neighbor’s yard, obviously I’m violating her sovereignty and the state has a legitimate right to constrain my liberty; no one would call that “paternalism.” But the causal chain between my decision to drink a big soda and the effect on health-care costs is long, tenuous, incremental, and uncertain. Perhaps I decided to jog home after my soda! Do I get a tax credit for that? In the case of soda, the claim to individual sovereignty is more immediate, more tangible, than the long thread connecting the decision to impacts on the collective welfare.
What this reveals is that state decisions to restrict individual behavior can not be guided by a clean line between the individual and collective spheres; there is no clean line. Restrictions on individual liberty will always be judgment calls about whether negative effects on others (externalities) outweigh the presumption of sovereignty.
This dilemma is on the mind of anyone who covers climate and energy.
I'll argue for two separate bright-line rules: the first based on individual rights (but pretty influenced by economics), and the second where I ditch the rights-based argument and stick to the economics.

Let's compare Roberts' first two examples, sticking to a rights-based approach for now; the pure economics version will be a separate post.

The only mechanism by which somebody else's obesity really hurts me is when either my insurer is legally barred from charging actuarially fair premiums, or when health care is covered through generalized taxes.* Let insurers charge the obese for their actual expected risk and there is no cost on anybody else. Let the government get out of the business of providing health care and instead get into the business of giving poor people money and mandating that they buy private health insurance with it, and obesity again puts no cost on anybody else. It's perverse to tell people:
"In exchange for forcing you to be part of a public insurance scheme that you might not want, I'm going to set up an apparatus of regulations, subsidies and taxes to force you to behave in ways that reduce the costs on the system that I'm forcing you to join. You're welcome."
Roberts' long causal chain runs directly through deliberate policy choices that work to socialise the costs of individual behaviour. And if we let things run through that mechanism, there is absolutely no end to the range of behaviours that can legitimately be subject to the heavy hand of the state. Remember that STDs cost the government money too.

By contrast, carbon emissions do affect others directly and in a way that's awfully hard to handle through tort. Setting up a clean carbon tax seems the best way of minimizing aggregate rights violations: the tax is an imposition, but so too are the emissions.

When we ditch the rights-talk and stick to economics, we have to look at pecuniary, non-pecuniary, and fiscal externalities. That's likely worth a separate post since it comes up an awful lot and I'd rather like to be able to point to it on its own in future. In short, the economic case for intervening in response to external effects depends not on whether other people are bearing costs but rather on whether there are efficiency consequences.

* There can be a case where the insurer is allowed to do it but it isn't worth the insurer's time and effort. Aggregate losses in this case can't be very large - the insurer doesn't spend much time assessing your risk of paper-cuts for similar reasons. The same holds for other kinds of transactions where there are apparent effects. Airlines have tried to require that very large people purchase two seats to accommodate their girth; some countries have socialised this cost by mandating that airlines give fat people two seats for the price of one; others have banned it as discriminatory. The obese cost you money in higher airfares because the government has forced the airline to make it so.

2 comments:

  1. "Let insurers charge the obese for their actual expected risk and there is no cost on anybody else. Let the government get out of the business of providing health care and instead get into the business of giving poor people money and mandating that they buy private health insurance with it, and obesity again puts no cost on anybody else."

    This is only true so long as the amount that the government gives people is not contingent upon lifestyle choices that might be correlated with health outcomes -- i.e. it needs to be moral hazard proof. I doubt most governments have the intestinal fortitudes to enact such policies, however.

    ReplyDelete